Wednesday, January 31, 2007

A Modest Proposal (HB 1707 and SB 5787)


The proposed legislation to prohibit death sentences for persons whose actions are the result of a severe mental illness is very modest proposal.


First, the definition of "severe mental illness" used in the bill is narrower than the current definition used in the approved list of mitigating factors. In other words, it is tougher to prove "severe mental illness" as a complete defense to the death penalty than it was to prove severe mental illness as a mitigating factor.


Next, our definition of "severe mental illness" constitutes insanity in seventeen states. In those states, a finding of severe mental illness would shield the defendant from any criminal liability, not just a possible death sentence.


In at least six additional states--Arizona, Florida, Indiana, Mississippi, Ohio and Nevada--proportionality review has served to remove many mentally ill offenders (where the existence of serious mental illness is not disputed) from the ranks of the condemned despite the apparent availability of capital punishment in such cases.


The current trend is to extend this prohibition. Like Washington State, Indiana does not recognize "severe mental illness" as a complete defense to murder. However, like us, Indiana is currently considering similar legislation to ban death sentences for the severely mentally ill.


If you add the states that have abolished the death penalty completely, it is clear that an overwhelming number of states have repudiated death sentences for persons who are severely mentally ill.


I hope that the time has come to add our great state to this list.

The Conversation

KUOW, local public radio, aired a discussion about the future of the death penalty in Washington State. You can listen to it here: http://www.kuow.org/programs/theconversation.asp

We're in the Senate!!


Our two bills (creating a task force to study the (mis)-use of the death penalty in this state and to prohibit the execution of severely mentally ill individuals) have been introduced in the Senate.

SB 5786 and 5787 are the same their counter-parts in the House.


Lethal Injection and National Death Penalty Trends


Stateline.org's report on national trends, includes an interesting section on the death penalty (beginning on p. 35). It also addresses problems state face in funding public education.

Hey, maybe if we got rid of the death penalty we could use that money for education....just a thought.

Tuesday, January 30, 2007

Reflections on a Maturing, Moral Society

Dan Rodricks, from the Baltimore Sun, has written a brilliant editorial, which includes this passage:

If an American ideal is that our society be less violent -- and I think we still want that, right? -- then we can't be authorizing executions.

Period.

Paragraph.

That's the moral burden of calling ours a civilized society.

If we all know and believe that violence begets violence, why do we give it our official approval? The death penalty makes hypocrites of us all.

You can read the entire editorial here: http://www.baltimoresun.com/news/local/bal-md.rodricks28jan28,1,2012226.column?coll=bal-local-storyutil&ctrack=1&cset=true

Monday, January 29, 2007

A Shout Out...

...to our friends at Capital Defense Weekly, who kindly said "hello" and promoted our bills (and blog) here: http://capitaldefenseweekly.com/

There is strength in our shared knowledge, resolute opposition to capital punshment, and the ever growing number of abolitionists.

Saturday, January 27, 2007

A colossal waste....

In 1991, James Brett killed Kenneth Milosevich.

In 1992, James Brett was convicted of murder and sentenced to death here in the State of Washington. Three years later, in 1995, his conviction was affirmed on direct appeal. Then, counsel was appointed to represent Brett in his Personal Restraint Petition. Here's what was discovered:

Dr. Julia T. Moore, a licensed, board-certified child and adult psychiatrist, reviewed Brett's Department of Juvenile Rehabilitation and school records, as well as other medical reports and records and affidavits from family members. She performed a clinical interview of Brett and concluded to a reasonable medical certainty that Brett suffered from bipolar disorder, fetal alcohol effect or alcohol-related neurodevelopmental disorder, and a psychiatric sequela as a consequence of poorly controlled diabetes. She further testified that Brett had suffered from bipolar disorder since at least age nine.

Dr. Robert A. Olsen, a board-certified medical doctor of internal medicine, psychiatry, and geriatric psychiatry, diagnosed Brett with "brittle" type 1 diabetes, a rare form of the disease, with severe medical and psychiatric consequences. Dr. Olsen testified that, in the short term, the disease could create wild fluctuations in blood sugar and could impair cognitive functions. In the long term, the disease could cause brain and heart damage, such as cognitive problems, dementia, coronary artery disease, peripheral vascular disease, and autonomic neuropathy. Brett's diabetic symptoms could have been aggravated by exposure to alcohol in childhood and throughout his adult life. Dr. Olsen concluded that the diabetes manifested itself when James Brett was nine years old.

Dr. Robin A. LaDue, a licensed clinical psychologist with a specialty in neuropsychology and renowned expert on fetal alcohol exposure, testified as to the impact of Brett's fetal alcohol condition. Dr. LaDue testified that Brett's fetal alcohol effect revealed "a pattern of brain damage most likely related to prenatal alcohol exposure." In her opinion, this brain damage had a "significant impact" on Brett's mental abilities, including his impaired judgment, his inability to understand cause and effect, and his difficulty controlling impulses.

None of this evidence was contested by the State.

None of this evidence had been presented to the jury that sentenced Brett to death.

So, in 2001, a decade after the crime, Brett's death sentence was overturned. He was later sentenced to life in prison.

While Brett's original trial attorneys should certainly be blamed for their negligence, you have to wonder if all of this could have been avoided if a law existed that made individuals, likes James Brett, who suffer from severe mental diabilities ineligible for a death sentence.

If we had such a law in 1991, could we have saved hundreds of thousands of dollars, avoided much anguish, and reached justice quicker? I think the obvious answer is "yes."

Before It's Too Late....



This is Robert "Eagle" Clayton, a Native American who was convicted of murder in the State of Oklahoma.

Clayton was also mentally retarded. A psychologist, who testified at the trial, assessed that he had an IQ of 68 (indicating a learning disability), a tendency to be dependent and submissive, and was emotionally immature. The son of alcoholic parents, Robert Clayton had dropped out of school when he was about 12 years old.

At the time of Robert's trial, there was no prohibition against the execution of individuals suffering from mental retardation. However, that changed on June 20, 2002, when the United States Supreme Court ruled (in a case entitled Atkins v. Virginia) that it violates our constitutional protections to execute someone who is "mentally retarded."

The Supreme Court ruling came too late for Clayton and those who knew him. Clayton was executed by the State of Oklahoma on February 2, 2001.

We need to pass a law preventing death sentences for the severely mentally ill before it's too late for someone else.....

Friday, January 26, 2007

Before It's Too Late...


This is Napoleon Beazley. Napoleon was 17 years old when he was convicted of murder and sentenced to death.
In 2004, the US Supreme Court accepted review and in 2005 ruled (in Roper v. Simmons) that the constitution prohibits death sentences for individuals who were juveniles at the time of their crimes.
Beazley made this same argument to the Supreme Court only two years earlier.
The decision in Roper v. Simmons came too late for Beazley. He was executed on May 28, 2002.
Let's pass a bill prohibiting death sentences for persons who are severely mentally ill before its too late for somebody else's son, brother, father, cousin, friend....

Indiana's Bill to Prohibit Death Sentences in Cases Involving Severe Mental ilness

The Indiana Legislature has introduced a bill similar to ours. You can read the text of the bill and follow its progess here:
http://www.in.gov/apps/lsa/session/billwatch/billinfo?year=2007&session=1&request=getBill&docno=24

The accompanying fiscal impact statement sets forth the savings that would result, if such a bill became law: http://www.in.gov/legislative/bills/2007/PDF/FISCAL/SB0024.001.pdf

A Gap in the Evolving Standards of Decency

The underlying rationale for prohibiting executions of the mentally retarded is just as compelling for prohibiting executions of the seriously mentally ill, namely evolving standards of decency.

A landmark decision in June 2002 finally outlawed the death penalty for people with mental retardation. In Atkins v. Virginia, the Supreme Court held by six votes to three that the execution of such offenders is an excessive sanction, violating the Eighth Amendment ban on "cruel and unusual punishments". The Court reasoned that mental retardation diminishes personal culpability, and renders the death penalty in the case of this category of offenders difficult to justify on deterrence and retribution grounds.

The Atkins ruling overturned a 1989 decision, Penry v. Lynaugh, by finding that "standards of decency" in the USA had evolved in the intervening years to the point at which a "national consensus" had emerged against such executions – primarily reflected in state-level legislation banning the execution of the mentally retarded. From an international human rights perspective, an encouraging footnote attached to the Atkins opinion acknowledged that "within the world community, the imposition of the death penalty for crimes committed by mentally retarded offenders is overwhelmingly disapproved."

On 1 March 2005, the US Supreme Court removed another category of defendant from the reach of the death penalty, namely children. In Roper v. Simmons, a majority of five Justices to four brought the USA into compliance with "the overwhelming weight of international opinion against the juvenile death penalty."

The Court "affirmed the necessity of referring to the evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society to determine which punishments are so disproportionate as to be cruel and unusual". In finding that the death penalty against offenders who were under 18 years old at the time of the crime was indeed excessive, the Roper majority quoted the Atkins decision: "Capital punishment must be limited to those offenders who commit a narrow category of the most serious crimes and whose extreme culpability makes them the most deserving of execution".

The Atkins and Roper decisions cannot but leave a question mark over another category of offender, namely the mentally ill. If the diminished culpability associated with youth and mental retardation render the death penalty an excessive punishment when used against offenders from those categories, what about people suffering from serious mental disorder other than retardation, such as serious brain damage, at the time of the crime? Should they not also be ineligible for execution? Justice Stevens, writing for the Supreme Court majority in Atkins, concluded that:

"Mentally retarded persons… have diminished capacities to understand and process information, to communicate, to abstract from mistakes and learn from experience, to engage in logical reasoning, to control impulses, and to understand the reactions of others. There is no evidence that they are more likely to engage in criminal conduct that others, but there is abundant evidence that they often act on impulse rather than pursuant to a premeditated plan…Their deficiencies do not warrant an exemption from criminal sanctions, but they do diminish their personal culpability."

While mental retardation and mental illness are not the same, the analysis given in the Atkins ruling nevertheless could be applied to the latter. For example, a mentally ill person’s delusional beliefs may cause them to engage in illogical reasoning and to act on impulse. A former President of the American Psychiatric Association wrote following the Atkins decision that:
"… the mentally ill suffer from many of the same limitations that, in Justice Stevens’ words, ‘do not warrant an exemption from criminal sanctions, but they do diminish their personal culpability".

Some judges in the USA have already recognized this fundamental inconsistency. In July 2003, for example, Judge Robert Henry on the US Court of Appeals for the 10th Circuit noted the Atkins ruling, and concluded that the imposition of the death penalty against Robert Bryan, a mentally ill Oklahoma death row inmate, "contributes nothing" to the goals of retribution and deterrence. Although Judge Henry was joined by three other judges on the court, it was not enough to stop Robert Bryan going to his execution in June 2004. In similar vein in September 2002, Justice Robert Rucker of the Indiana Supreme Court dissented against the death sentence of Joseph Corcoran, an Indiana inmate suffering from mental illness including schizophrenia. Justice Rucker drew attention to the Atkins decision:

"I respectfully dissent because I do not believe a sentence of death is appropriate for a person suffering a severe mental illness. Recently the Supreme Court held that the executions of mentally retarded criminals are ‘cruel and unusual punishments’ prohibited by the Eighth Amendment of the United States Constitution. There has been no argument in this case that Corcoran is mentally retarded. However, the underlying rationale for prohibiting executions of the mentally retarded is just as compelling for prohibiting executions of the seriously mentally ill, namely evolving standards of decency".

Washington State Bar Assocication's Death Penalty Subcommittee's Report

Death Penalty Subcommittee of the Committee on Public Defense Final Report
The Death Penalty Subcommittee of the Committee on Public Defense has issued its Final Report. It will be submitted to the WSBA Board of Governors along with the full report of the Committee on Public Defense at the Board meeting on March 2 – 3, 2007. The Death Penalty Subcommittee Report discusses how the death penalty has operated in Washington, the costs of death penalty cases, and compensation of attorneys in death penalty cases. It makes nine recommendations regarding the death penalty in Washington.

Read Full Report: http://www.wsba.org/lawyers/groups/finalreport.pdf

Study Bill--Read the results of the NJ Death Penalty Comm study

We have introduced a bill to undertake a study of Washington's death penalty. A similar study group was formed in New Jersey and recently complete their report.

The NJ Commission recommended abolishing the death penalty and replacing it with life without parole. You can read their report here:

http://www.njleg.state.nj.us/committees/dpsc_final.pdf

Why We Should Not Kill Severely Mentally Ill Persons

Excerpts from a law review article:

Jamie Wilson, nineteen years old and severely mentally ill, walked into a school cafeteria and started shooting. Two children died, and Jamie was charged with two counts of capital murder. Because he admitted his guilt, the only issue at his trial was the appropriate punishment. The trial judge assigned to his case, after hearing expert testimony on his mental state, found that mental illness rendered Jamie unable to conform his conduct to the requirements of law at the time of the crime--not impaired by his mental illness in his ability to control his behavior, but unable to control his behavior. The following day, the same judge sentenced Jamie to death.

The most common reaction to Jamie's story, regardless of the death penalty views of the audience, is "What?" At the very least, it is counterintuitive to kill someone for behavior he was powerless to avoid. Whether a practice is unconstitutional, of course, is hardly determined by whether it is sensible, and the South Carolina Supreme Court has held that, sensible or not, it is constitutional. In so holding, the fact that no other defendant--in South Carolina or any other state--has ever been sentenced to death after the factfinder determined that he lacked volitional control did not sway the court.

Thursday, January 25, 2007

Austin American-Statesman Editorial on Patterson and Mentally Ill Defendants

Finding justice for mentally ill defendants

Written by: Editorial Board, Austin American-Statesman

May 10, 2004: Austin American-Statesman

Finding justice for mentally ill defendants

There is little doubt that Texas will execute Kelsey Patterson on May 18 if left to its own devices. Neither is there doubt that Patterson is guilty of murdering two East Texans. Even so, this case never should have reached this point, given that Patterson is severely mentally ill.In 1992, Patterson was wandering the streets with a hand gun when he happened upon Louis Oates, a Palestine businessman, and fatally shot him. When Oates' secretary ran out from the office, Patterson also killed her. Patterson, who lived in the same town, barely knew them.
Following the shootings, he walked back to his nearby home, stripped to his socks and walked naked in the streets until police arrived. Prosecutors have yet to establish a motive in the double homicide.

Patterson was in and out of state mental hospitals during the 1980s following random acts of violence linked to schizophrenia when he failed to take his medication. He was released after being subdued with medication and treatment. The system would restart.

His case reveals anew a deep breach in the justice system and a breakdown in the state's mental health system. After the first relapse, Patterson should have been committed long term, or at the minimum, been watched closely. Patterson's claim of being a paranoid schizophrenic is not a ruse. The history and evidence of his mental illness is so compelling that it troubled one of the most conservative members of the 5th U.S. Circuit Court of Appeals."What are we doing here?" Judge Edith Jones asked Assistant Attorney General Gina Bunn, who defended the state's decision to execute Patterson before a panel of the federal court. "This is a very sick man."

The cycle of violence exhibited in Patterson's case is all too familiar. We recently heard the tragic story of a Beaumont man, Kenneth Lee Pierott, charged with murder in the asphyxiation of a 6-year-old boy in an oven, six years after a jury found the Pierott innocent by reason of insanity of beating his disabled sister to death. Deanna Laney, a Tyler mother, was found innocent of murdering two of her three children because she was insane. And there is the case of University of Texas graduate student Jackson Ngai, who is accused of using a meat cleaver to kill a UT professor. Ngai told police he was trying to remove a computer chip from her brain.

Obviously, the system is failing. A legislative committee is studying whether to revise Texas law so that a jury could find such people guilty but insane, allowing severely mentally ill people to be closely supervised and treated in secure settings. That won't satisfy everyone. But it is surely better than executing mentally ill people who repeatedly commit violent crimes or locking them away in regular prisons without adequate treatment. In Patterson's case, lawyers are scrambling to win an appeal, or at least a stay, asserting that Patterson is legally incompetent to be executed. He was found to be sane at the time of his 1992 crime by an East Texas court that sentenced him to death. Patterson believes that a foreign device, implanted in his body, is being used by evil forces to control him and do him harm. The conspiracy against him takes the form of the "hell pledge" inscribed in a secret book. And nearly everyone, from the judges and doctors affiliated with his case to the lawyers who represent him, are "hell workers."Patterson believes their purpose is to carry out the pledge against him, and consequently, has refused to cooperate with mental health experts and his lawyers.

His fate now rests with federal courts. It's clear that executing him won't resolve the issue of how to protect society from severely mentally ill people who turn violent. That is an issue for the Legislature.

Addendum: Patterson was executed on May 18, 2004, despite a recommendation for clemency. The system can just as easily fail here, which is why we need legislation.

Executing the Mentally Ill Article from Amnesty International Magazine, Fall 2005

Cruel and Inhumane
Executing the Mentally Ill

Recent U.S. Supreme Court rulings barring executions of juvenile offenders and people with mental retardation have given death penalty opponents hope that the mentally ill may someday also be spared. But the issue raises difficult questions for lawmakers and courts.
By Dan Malone

Dan Malone, a staff writer at Fort Worth Weekly, is co-author of America's Condemned: Death Row Inmates in Their Own Words (Andrews McMeel, 1999).

Little about Kelsey Patterson's disturbing life made sense. He was repeatedly arrested for a series of increasingly violent assaults and shootings, repeatedly diagnosed as mentally ill, repeatedly admitted to mental institutions and repeatedly released-only to be arrested yet again for another act of senseless violence.
He was arrested for the final time on a warm September afternoon in east Texas in 1992. Police found Patterson walking naked down the street near his home, mumbling and gesturing to people along the way. No clear motive for his crime-a double murder-was ever established. A jury subsequently sentenced him to death.
During his 12 years on Texas' death row, Patterson, who was first diagnosed as a paranoid schizophrenic in 1981, frequently complained about a remote control device implanted in his body, refused to cooperate with his lawyers and insisted until his death that he had received a permanent stay of execution. As he lay strapped to a gurney in the death house, he responded "state what" when asked if he had a final statement, then launched into an incoherent, profane ramble, his last words as confusing as the jumble of his 50 years of life.
Today, a little more than a year after his execution, advocates for the mentally ill contend that the execution of Patterson and other mentally ill prisoners make even less sense than the gnarled paths of their lives.
Two recent U.S. Supreme Court rulings barring executions of juvenile offenders and people with mental retardation have given death penalty opponents hope that others with diminished capacity for judgment will also be spared the fate of a punishment they may not even comprehend. In both decisions the Court sought to bring current state practice in line with "evolving standards of decency." Some experts believe the recent rulings have bolstered the legal basis for protecting the mentally ill.
"It all has to do with their ability to form what we consider to be adult conceptions of morality and responsibility," says Bill Harris, a Texas attorney who represented Larry Keith Robison, a schizophrenic who was executed in 2001 for killing five people during a psychotic episode nearly 20 years earlier. "If you say it's cruel and unusual to execute the mentally retarded because they can't perform on an adult level, and then you say the same thing about people who are mentally normal but because of their age you can't execute them, it makes sense to extend that to mental illness."
"If it impairs their ability to make those kind of moral judgments, they should also be, logically, exempt."
On March 1 the Supreme Court categorically banned the death penalty for juvenile offenders under age 18 in Roper v. Simmons. By the time the Court heard the case of Christopher Simmons, a Missouri inmate who had been sentenced to death for a murder he committed when he was 17 year old, 30 states had already banned the practice and most others had turned their backs on it. The decision did, however, overturn the sentences of 72 death row inmates in 12 states who were convicted of committing crimes as teenagers. (The death penalty for federal crimes was forbidden for offenders under the age of 18.)
Juveniles, the court said, are vulnerable and lack the maturity and fully developed character of adults. "Their own vulnerability and comparative lack of control over their immediate surroundings mean that juveniles have a greater claim than adults to be forgiven?" That majority opinion also cited an emergent national consensus, and significantly, an international one that left the United States "alone in a world that has turned its face against the juvenile death penalty."
The Simmons challenge followed another milestone Supreme Court decision, Atkins v. Virginia, which banned the execution of those with mental retardation. The 2002 ruling dealt with the case of Daryl Renard Atkins, who was sentenced to die in Virginia for the 1996 murder of Eric Nesbitt, a 21-year-old U.S. airman. Testimony about Atkins' mental abilities conflicted wildly. Defense witnesses told jurors Atkins was "mildly mentally retarded" and functioned at the level of a 9- to 12-year-old. A prosecution expert countered that Atkins suffered from a antisocial personality disorder and was of "average intelligence, at least." The Court banned the execution of those with mental retardation, citing a "dramatic shift" in how state law dealt with offenders with mental retardation- close to 20 states had already revised their laws to end executions of mentally retarded offenders. And officials in the remaining states had executed only a handful of persons with mental retardation since the late 1980s. However, while the Supreme Court sided with Atkins' lawyers in ruling that executing those with mental retardation is unconstitutionally cruel, the Court did not decide whether Atkins has a mental disability. That determination was left to the commonwealth of Virginia, and, at press time, Atkins was on trial to establish his IQ.
Execution of severely mentally retarded people, wrote Justice John Paul Stevens in Atkins v. Virginia, "has become truly unusual, and it is fair to say that a national consensus has developed against it."
Neither ruling specifically addressed mental illness. But Victor Streib, an Ohio Northern University law professor who was quoted 11 times by the Supreme Court in the case barring juvenile executions, also believes that mentally ill prisoners should not be subjected to the death penalty.
"The general public too often assumes that only the seriousness of the crime is relevant to the punishment, but the (Supreme) Court has repeatedly held that both the serious(ness) of the crime and the character and background of the defendant must be considered in the sentencing decision," he said.
"If certain mentally ill defendants think and act like juveniles or the mentally retarded, then they should be excluded from death row."
In practice, applying the Simmons ruling on juveniles is straightforward. "With juveniles, you are either 18 or you're not," says Gary Hart, the Texas attorney who represented Kelsey Patterson in his final appeals.
Mental retardation is thornier territory. "There is a misrepresentation that since Atkins had been handed down there is no longer any danger of people with mental retardation being executed," says Ronald Tabak, a New York attorney who serves on a task force, created by the American Bar Association (ABA) Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities, that is examining capital punishment for mentally ill defendants. "In fact, it's a great danger. I'd say it's a certainty." Lawyers for some capital defendants never discover that their clients have mental retardation, while others may know the condition exists but lack the resources to prove it. Some states even lack a clear definition of mental retardation or a process for raising it during the various stages of a trial.
Extending protection to the mentally ill could prove to be even more complicated. "With mental retardation, there is at least some agreement about what constitutes mental retardation. With mental illness, you've got such a wide spectrum, everything from depression to bi-polar to post-traumatic stress syndrome, to paranoid schizophrenia. It's a much more difficult thing to know where and how to draw the line," says Hart.
"I'm not sure I would know how to draw the line," he says.
The prospect of drawing any lines with regard to mental illness raises daunting questions: What sort of mental illnesses might qualify accused killers the same protections given to juveniles and those with mental retardation? How many people would be affected by such a prohibition? What sort of changes would be needed in state law for such a prohibition to be imposed? And what about those prisoners who might have been sane when they committed their crimes but became mentally ill during years or decades they spent on death row?
The ABA task force has come up with several proposals that have won endorsements from professional organizations such as the National Alliance for the Mentally Ill, the American Psychological Association and the American Psychiatric Association.
One proposal would protect from capital punishment those with serious mental illnesses, such as schizophrenia, that significantly impaired their ability to reason at the time of their crime. These prisoners are, according to Tabak, "categorically less culpable than so-called average murderers."
Another set of proposals addresses situations in which mental illness precludes condemned prisoners from assisting in their own defenses, causes them to waive their appeals or prevents those facing imminent execution unable to understand what is about to happen to them, or why.
"We are not trying to excuse the misconduct of these people," Tabak explains. "If we were trying to do that, we wouldn't allow them to be punished at all." But, he says, "the extent of blameworthiness, the extent to which they can be held among what's sometimes called 'the worst of the worst,' is diminished by their mental illness."
Opponents to the proposal contend that mentally ill people are sufficiently protected under existing law.
"Someone who commits a crime because of mental illness-who didn't know right from wrong or didn't know what they were doing-is going to be found not guilty by reason of insanity," says Larry Cunningham, a former prosecutor for the commonwealth of Virginia and law professor at Texas Tech and Texas Wesleyan Universities. "If a mentally ill individual has been found guilty and received the death penalty, they probably presented the insanity defense and lost."
Attorneys for a person convicted of a capital crime can still argue during a trial's punishment phase that a client is more deserving of a life sentence than the death penalty because of their mental illness.
"It's better to let a jury decide as we do right now," Cunningham says.
"Should crazy people be executed?" asks Joshua Marquis, district attorney of Clatsop County, Ore., and the chairman of the capital litigation committee of the National Association of District Attorneys. "The accepted answer to that is no."
But arguing that mentally ill offenders should be treated like juveniles or people with mental retardation is, he says, an "incredibly incremental abolitionist argument.'
"The vast majority of people on death row suffer from a mental disorder of some kind," Marquis said. "If you define it that way, nobody would ever be given the death penalty. It creates a standard that would effectively exempt anyone."
Theoretically, some of the most severely mentally ill inmates are protected by a 1986 Supreme Court ruling, Ford v. Wainwright, that forbids capital punishment of those who are so insane that they cannot comprehend their impending execution or the reasons for it. Citing the Eighth Amendment, the decision blocked Florida from executing Alvin Ford, a man convicted of murder who became insane while on death row. Justice Lewis Powell drew his own line, reasoning that the Constitution protected only those who are so insane that they are "unaware of the punishment they are about to suffer and why they are to suffer it. Justice Powell concluded that Florida could execute Ford if he became sane again, presenting a cruel irony: death row inmates who become insane must remain insane to avoid execution. Moreover, the Ford decision left the determination of sanity up to each state and herein lies the heart of the problem.
At the time of the ruling, about a dozen of more than 1,700 death row inmates had insanity assertions made on their behalf, according to the New York Times. Today, it is difficult to say with any certainty how many on death row are mentally ill. The American Civil Liberties Union estimates that up to 10 percent of the more than 3,400 inmates on the nation's death rows have a serious mental illness. Other research conducted in the mid 1990s indicates the problem could be much larger. The Dallas Morning News reported in 1997 that one-third of 602 death row inmates nationwide who responded to the newspaper's questionnaire had been treated for psychiatric problems ranging from suicide and depression to anti-social behavior and sexual problems.
Whatever the actual numbers might be, mental health experts believe that many mentally ill prisoners would never have made it to death row in the first place if they had been able to find treatment when they were free.
Texas executed on March 26, 2003, James Blake Colburn, a 43-year-old mentally ill man who heard voices and worried about demons defiling his corpse, despite his failed, repeated attempts to get help before he murdered Peggy Murphy. "We begged for help," his sister, Tina Duroy told Amnesty International a year before his execution. "He himself wanted help, and they ... just pushed him out on the street."
The state of Texas, which ranks number one in number of people executed, ranked 46th among the states for amount of money spent per person on the treatment of the mentally ill, including in jails and prisons, according to the National Association of State Mental Health Program Directors.
Amnesty International is beginning to collect data from death row states about mental health spending and the number of mentally ill condemned prisoners. AI researchers are also investigating cases in which families of mentally ill death row inmates tried long ago to get help but were denied because they didn't have the funds or the right insurance.
Sue Gunawardena-Vaughn, director of Amnesty International USA's Program to Abolish the Death Penalty, says states need to "put more money into mental health care so those crimes don't happen in the first place."
The failure to adequately fund mental health services throughout the states imperils more than just the mentally ill, said Hazel Moran of the National Mental Health Association. Every mentally ill person behind bars leaves victims — living or dead — in the free world.
Lot of people are winding up in the criminal justice system because mental health services are not available," she said. "Because the mental health system does not have the resources, a person doesn't have the opportunity to get better and, as a result, they wind up following a path that leads to a bad outcome.
"We think that's a systemic failure."
Gunawardena-Vaughn echoes that belief.
"A society that denies mental health care to those who need it the most and then subsequently executes them is cruel and inhumane at its very core. All of us need to be asking, 'Is this the kind of society that we envision for ourselves?' My answer is that we can and must do better."

National Alliance on Mental Illness (NAMI)

http://www.nami.org/

American Bar Association Resolution 122A

AMERICAN BAR ASSOCIATION SECTION OF INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS AND RESPONSIBILITIESCRIMINAL JUSTICE SECTIONCOMMISSION ON MENTAL AND PHYSICAL DISABILITY LAW
ABA DEATH PENALTY MORATORIUM IMPLEMENTATION PROJECT
ABA DEATH PENALTY REPRESENTATION PROJECT
BEVERLY HILLS BAR ASSOCIATIONRECOMMENDATION

RESOLVED, That the American Bar Association, without taking a position supporting or opposing the death penalty, urges each jurisdiction that imposes capital punishment to implement the following policies and procedures:
1. Defendants should not be executed or sentenced to death if, at the time of the offense, they had significant limitations in both their intellectual functioning and adaptive behavior, as expressed in conceptual, social, and practical adaptive skills, resulting from mental retardation, dementia, or a traumatic brain injury.
2. Defendants should not be executed or sentenced to death if, at the time of the offense, they had a severe mental disorder or disability that significantly impaired their capacity (a) to appreciate the nature, consequences or wrongfulness of their conduct, (b) to exercise rational judgment in relation to conduct, or (c) to conform their conduct to the requirements of the law. A disorder manifested primarily by repeated criminal conduct or attributable solely to the acute effects of voluntary use of alcohol or other drugs does not, standing alone, constitute a mental disorder or disability for purposes of this provision.
3. Mental Disorder or Disability after Sentencing
(a) Grounds for Precluding Execution. A sentence of death should not be carried out if the prisoner has a mental disorder or disability that significantly impairs his or her capacity (i) to make a rational decision to forgo or terminate post-conviction proceedings available to challenge the validity of the conviction or sentence; (ii) to understand or communicate pertinent information, or otherwise assist counsel, in relation to specific claims bearing on the validity of the conviction or sentence that cannot be fairly resolved without the prisoner's participation; or (iii) to understand the nature and purpose of the punishment, or to appreciate the reason for its imposition in the prisoner's own case. Procedures to be followed in each of these categories of cases are specified in (b) through (d) below.
(b) Procedure in Cases Involving Prisoners Seeking to Forgo or Terminate Post-Conviction Proceedings. If a court finds that a prisoner under sentence of death who
wishes to forgo or terminate post-conviction proceedings has a mental disorder or disability that significantly impairs his or her capacity to make a rational decision, the court should permit a next friend acting on the prisoner's behalf to initiate or pursue available remedies to set aside the conviction or death sentence.
(c) Procedure in Cases Involving Prisoners Unable to Assist Counsel in Post-Conviction Proceedings. If a court finds at any time that a prisoner under sentence of death has a mental disorder or disability that significantly impairs his or her capacity to understand or communicate pertinent information, or otherwise to assist counsel, in connection with post-conviction proceedings, and that the prisoner's participation is necessary for a fair resolution of specific claims bearing on the validity of the conviction or death sentence, the court should suspend the proceedings. If the court finds that there is no significant likelihood of restoring the prisoner's capacity to participate in post-conviction proceedings in the foreseeable future, it should reduce the prisoner's sentence to the sentence imposed in capital cases when execution is not an option.
(d) Procedure in Cases Involving Prisoners Unable to Understand the Punishment or its Purpose. If, after challenges to the validity of the conviction and death sentence have been exhausted and execution has been scheduled, a court finds that a prisoner has a mental disorder or disability that significantly impairs his or her capacity to understand the nature and purpose of the punishment, or to appreciate the reason for its imposition in the prisoner's own case, the sentence of death should be reduced to the sentence imposed in capital cases when execution is not an option.
REPORT
PREAMBLE
In Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002), the United States Supreme Court held that execution of people with mental retardation violates the Eighth Amendment's ban on cruel and unusual punishment. The Individual Rights and Responsibilities Section of the American Bar Association recognized that Atkins offered a timely opportunity to consider the extent, if any, to which other types of impaired mental conditions ought to lead to exemption from the death penalty. To achieve that objective, the Section established a Task Force on Mental Disability and the Death Penalty. The Task Force, which carried out its deliberations from April, 2003 to March, 2005, was composed of 24 lawyers and mental health professionals (both practitioners and academics), and included members of the American Psychiatric Association and the American Psychological Association.[1] The American Psychiatric Association[2] and the American Psychological Association[3] have officially endorsed the Task Force's proposal.[4] The following commentary discusses the three paragraphs of the proposal.
PARAGRAPH 1:
Paragraph 1 of the Recommendation is meant to exempt from the death penalty persons charged with capital offenses who have significant limitations in both intellectual functioning and adaptive skills. Its primary purpose is to implement the United States Supreme Court's holding in Atkins v. Virginia,[5] which declared that execution of offenders with mental retardation violates the cruel and unusual punishment prohibition in the Eighth Amendment. The Court based this decision both on a determination that a "national consensus" had been reached that people with mental retardation should not be executed,[6] and on its own conclusion that people with retardation who kill are not as culpable or deterrable as the "average murderer," much less the type of murderer for whom the death penalty may be viewed as justifiable.[7]
While the Atkins Court clearly prohibited execution of people with mental retardation, it did not define that term. The Recommendation embraces the language most recently endorsed by the American Association of Mental Retardation, which defines mental retardation as a disability originating before the age of eighteen that is "characterized by significant limitations both in intellectual functioning and in adaptive behavior as expressed in conceptual, social, and practical adaptive skills."[8] The language of the Recommendation is also consistent with the most recent edition of the American Psychiatric Association's Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, which defines a person as mentally retarded if, before the age of 18, he or she exhibits "significantly subaverage intellectual functioning" (defined as "an IQ of approximately 70 or below") and "concurrent deficits or impairments in present adaptive functioning . . . in at least two of the following areas: communication, self-care, home living, social/interpersonal skills, use of community resources, self-direction, functional academic skills, work, leisure, health, and safety."[9] Both of these definitions were referenced (albeit not explicitly endorsed) by the Supreme Court in Atkins, and both have been models for states that have defined retardation for purposes of the death penalty exemption.[10] Both capture the universe of people who, if involved in crime, Atkins describes as less culpable and less deterrable than the "average murderer." As the APA's Diagnostic and Statistical Manual indicates, even a person with only "mild" mental retardation, as that term is defined in the Manual, has a mental age below that of a teenager.[11]
The language in this part of the Recommendation is also meant to encompass dementia and traumatic brain injury, disabilities very similar to mental retardation in their impact on intellectual and adaptive functioning except that they always (in the case of dementia) or often (in the case of head injury) are manifested after age eighteen. Dementia resulting from the aging process is generally progressive and irreversible, and is associated with a number of deficits in intellectual and adaptive functioning, such as agnosia (failure to recognize or identify objects) and disturbances in executive functioning connected with planning, organizing, sequencing, and abstracting.[12] The same symptoms can be experienced by people with serious brain injury. Of course, people with dementia or a traumatic head injury severe enough to result in "significant limitations in both intellectual functioning or adaptive behavior" rarely commit capital offenses. If they do, however, the reasoning in Atkins should apply and an exemption from the death penalty is warranted, because the only significant characteristic that differentiates these severe disabilities from mental retardation is the age of onset.[13]

PARAGRAPH 2:
Paragraph 2 of the Recommendation is meant to prohibit execution of persons with severe mental disabilities whose demonstrated impairments of mental and emotional functioning at the time of the offense would render a death sentence disproportionate to their culpability. The Recommendation uses the phrase "disorder or disability" because, even though those words are often used interchangeably, some prefer one over the other. The Recommendation indicates that only those individuals with "severe" disorders or disabilities are to be exempted from the death penalty, and it specifically excludes from the exemption those diagnosed with conditions that are primarily manifested by criminal behavior and those whose abuse of psychoactive substances, standing alone, renders them impaired at the time of the offense.
Rationale: This part of the Recommendation is based on long-established principles of Anglo-American law that the Supreme Court recognized and embraced in Atkins and recently affirmed in Roper v. Simmons,[14] in which it held that the execution of juveniles who commit crimes while under the age of eighteen is prohibited by the Eighth Amendment. In reaching its holding in Atkins, the Court emphasized that execution of people with mental retardation is inconsistent with both the retributive and deterrent functions of the death penalty. More specifically, as noted above, it held that people with mental retardation who kill are both less culpable and less deterrable than the average murderer, because of their "diminished capacities to understand and process information, to communicate, to abstract from mistakes and learn from experience, to engage in logical reasoning, to control impulses, and to understand the reactions of others."[15] As the Court noted, "[i]f the culpability of the average murderer is insufficient to justify the most extreme sanction available to the State, the lesser culpability of the mentally retarded offender surely does not merit that form of retribution."[16] Similarly, with respect to deterrence, the Court stated, "[e]xempting the mentally retarded from [the death penalty] will not affect the 'cold calculus that precedes the decision' of other potential murderers."[17]
The Court made analogous observations in Simmons. With respect to culpability, the Court stated:
Whether viewed as an attempt to express the community's moral outrage or as an attempt to right the balance for the wrong to the victim, the case for retribution is not as strong with a minor as with an adult. Retribution is not proportional if the law's most severe penalty is imposed on one whose culpability or blameworthiness is diminished, to a substantial degree, by reason of youth and immaturity.[18]
On the deterrence issue it said, "'[t]he likelihood that the teenage offender has made the kind of cost-benefit analysis that attaches any weight to the possibility of execution is so remote as to be virtually nonexistent.'"[19]
The same reasoning applies to people who, in the words of the Recommendation, have a "severe mental disorder or disability" that, at the time of the offense: "significantly impaired their capacity" (1) "to appreciate the nature, consequences, or wrongfulness of their conduct"; (2) "to exercise rational judgment in relation to the conduct"; or (3) "to conform their conduct to the requirements of law." Offenders who meet these requirements, even if found sane at trial, are not as culpable or deterrable as the average offender. A close examination of this part of the Recommendation makes clear why this is so.
The Severe Mental Disorder or Disability Requirement. First, the predicate for exclusion from capital punishment under this part of the Recommendation is that offenders have a "severe" disorder or disability, which is meant to signify a disorder that is roughly equivalent to disorders that mental health professionals would consider the most serious "Axis I diagnoses."[20] These disorders include schizophrenia and other psychotic disorders, mania, major depressive disorder, and dissociative disorders – with schizophrenia being by far the most common disorder seen in capital defendants. In their acute state, all of these disorders are typically associated with delusions (fixed, clearly false beliefs), hallucinations (clearly erroneous perceptions of reality), extremely disorganized thinking, or very significant disruption of consciousness, memory and perception of the environment.[21] Some conditions that are not considered an Axis I condition might also, on rare occasions, become "severe" as that word is used in this Recommendation. For instance, some persons whose predominant diagnosis is a personality disorder, which is an Axis II disorder, may at times experience more significant dysfunction. Thus, people with borderline personality disorder can experience "psychotic-like symptoms ... during times of stress."[22] However, only if these more serious symptoms occur at the time of the capital offense would the predicate for this Recommendation's exemption be present.
The Significant Impairment Requirement. To ensure that the exemption only applies to offenders less culpable and less deterrable than the average murderer, this part of the Recommendation further requires that the disorder significantly impair cognitive or volitional functioning at the time of the offense. Atkins held the death penalty excessive for every person with mental retardation, and the Supreme Court therefore dispensed with a case-by-case assessment of responsibility. However, for the disorders covered by this second part of the Recommendation, preclusion of a death sentence based on diagnosis alone would not be sensible, because the symptoms of these disorders are much more variable than those associated with retardation or the other disabilities covered by the Recommendation's first paragraph.
The first specific type of impairment that this part of the Recommendation recognizes as a basis for exemption from the death penalty (if there was a severe disorder at the time of the offense) is a significant incapacity "to appreciate the nature, consequences, or wrongfulness" of the conduct associated with the offense (section (a)). This provision is meant to encompass those individuals with severe disorder who have serious difficulty appreciating the wrongfulness of their criminal conduct. For instance, people who, because of psychosis, erroneously perceived their victims to be threatening them with serious harm would be covered by this language,[23] as would delusional offenders who believed that God had ordered them to commit the offense.[24]
Section (a) also refers to offenders who fail to appreciate the "nature and consequences" of the crime. This language would clearly apply to offenders who, because of severe disorder or disability, did not intend to engage in the conduct constituting the crime or were unaware they were committing it.[25] It would also apply to delusional offenders who intended to commit the crime and knew that the conduct was wrongful, but experienced confusion and self-referential thinking that prevented them from recognizing its full ramifications. For example, a person who experiences delusional beliefs that electric power lines are implanting demonic curses, and thus comes to believe that he or she must blow up a city's power station, might understand that destruction of property and taking the law into one's own hands is wrong but might nonetheless fail to appreciate that the act would harm and perhaps kill those who relied on the electricity.
The second type of impairment recognized as a basis for exemption from the death penalty under this part of the Recommendation (in section (b)) is a significant incapacity "to exercise rational judgment in relation to the conduct" at the time of the crime. Numerous commentators have argued that irrationality is the core determinant of diminished responsibility.[26] As used by these commentators, and as made clear by the Recommendation's threshold requirement of severe mental disability, "irrational" judgment in this context does not mean "inaccurate," "unusual" or "bad" judgment. Rather, it refers to the type of disoriented, incoherent and delusional thinking that only people with serious mental disability experience. Furthermore, as noted above, the Recommendation requires that the irrationality occur in connection with the offense, rather than simply have existed prior to the criminal conduct.
Under these conditions, offenders who come within section (b) would often also fail to appreciate the "nature, consequences, or wrongfulness" of their conduct. But there is a subset of severely impaired individuals who may not meet the latter test and yet who should still be exempted from the death penalty because they are clearly not as culpable or deterrable as the average murderer. For instance, a jury rejected Andrea Yates' insanity defense despite strong evidence of psychosis at the time she drowned her five children. Apparently, the jury believed that, even though her delusions existed at the time of the offense, she could still appreciate the wrongfulness (and maybe even the fatal consequences) of her acts. Yet that same jury spared Yates the death penalty, probably because it believed her serious mental disorder significantly impaired her ability to exercise rational judgment in relation to the conduct.[27]
The third and final type of offense-related impairment recognized as a basis for exemption from the death penalty by this part of the Recommendation is a significant incapacity "to conform [one's] conduct to the requirements of law" (section (c)). Most people who meet this definition will probably also experience significant cognitive impairment at the time of the crime. However, some may not. For example, people who have a mood disorder with psychotic features might understand the wrongfulness of their acts and their consequences, but nonetheless feel impervious to punishment because of delusion-inspired grandiosity.[28] Because a large number of offenders can make plausible claims that they felt compelled to commit their crime, however, enforcement of the Recommendation's requirement that impairment arise from a "severe" disorder is especially important here.
Exclusions. In addition to the severe disability threshold and the requirement of significant cognitive or volitional impairment at the time of the offense, a third way this part of the Recommendation assures that those it exempts from the death penalty are less culpable and deterrable than the average murderer is to exclude explicitly from its coverage those offenders whose disorder is "manifested primarily by repeated criminal conduct or attributable solely to the acute effects of voluntary use of alcohol or other drugs." The Recommendation's reference to mental disorders "manifested primarily by repeated criminal conduct" is meant to deny the death penalty exemption to those offenders whose only diagnosis is Antisocial Personality Disorder.[29] This language is virtually identical to language in the Model Penal Code's insanity formulation, which was designed to achieve the same purpose.[30] However, the Recommendation uses the word "primarily" where the MPC uses the word "solely" because Antisocial Personality Disorder consists of a number of symptom traits in addition to antisocial behavior, and therefore the MPC language does not achieve its intended effect. Compared to the MPC's provision, then, the Recommendation's language broadens the category of offenders whose responsibility is not considered sufficiently diminished to warrant exemption from capital punishment.
Similarly, the Recommendation denies the death penalty exemption to those offenders who lack appreciation or control of their actions at the time of the offense due "solely to the acute effects of voluntary use of alcohol or other drugs." Substance abuse often plays a role in crime. When voluntary ingestion of psychoactive substances compromises an offender's cognitive or volitional capacities, the law sometimes is willing to reduce the grade of offense at trial, especially in murder cases,[31] and evidence of intoxication should certainly be taken into account if it is offered in mitigation in a capital sentencing proceeding.[32] However, in light of the wide variability in the effects of alcohol and other drugs on mental and emotional functioning, voluntary intoxication alone does not warrant an automatic exclusion from the death penalty.[33] At the same time, this Recommendation is not meant to prevent exemption from the death penalty for those offenders whose substance abuse has caused organic brain disorders or who have other serious disorders that, in combination with the acute effects of substance abuse, significantly impaired appreciation or control at the time of the offense.[34]
How This Recommendation Relates to the Insanity Defense. The language proposed in this part of the Recommendation is similar to modern formulations of the insanity defense.[35] Nonetheless, in light of the narrow reach of the defense in most states (and its abolition in a few),[36] many offenders who meet these criteria will still be convicted rather than acquitted by reason of insanity. Even in those states with insanity formulations that are very similar to the Recommendation's language, these individuals might be convicted, for a whole host of reasons;[37] in such cases, the Recommendation would require juries and judges to consider whether cognitive and volitional impairment removes the defendant from being among the most morally culpable offenders. This approach rests on the traditional understanding that significant cognitive or volitional impairment attributable to a severe disorder or disability often renders the death penalty disproportionate to the defendant's culpability, even though the offender may still be held accountable for the crime.[38] It also underlies the various formulations of diminished responsibility that predated the contemporary generation of capital sentencing statutes.[39]
How This Recommendation Relates to Mitigating Factors. This part of the Recommendation sets up, in effect, a conclusive "defense" against the death penalty for capital defendants who can demonstrate the requisite level of impairment due to severe disorder at the time of the offense. However, the criteria in the Recommendation do not exhaust the relevance of mental disorder or disability in capital sentencing. Those offenders whose mental disorder or disability at the time of the offense was not severe or did not cause one of the enumerated impairments would still be entitled to argue that their mental dysfunction is a mitigating factor, to be considered with aggravating factors and other mitigating factors in determining whether capital punishment should be imposed.[40]
PARAGRAPH 3:
This paragraph of the Recommendation is meant to address three different circumstances under which concerns about a prisoner's mental competence and suitability for execution arise after the prisoner has been sentenced to death. Subpart (a) states that execution should be precluded when a prisoner lacks the capacity (i) to make a rational decision regarding whether to pursue post-conviction proceedings, (ii) to assist counsel in post-conviction adjudication, or (iii) to appreciate the meaning or purpose of an impending execution. The succeeding subparts spell out the conditions under which execution should be barred in these three situations.
Prisoners Seeking to Forgo or Terminate Post-Conviction Proceedings. The United States Supreme Court has ruled that a competent prisoner is entitled to forgo available appeals.[41] If the prisoner is not competent, the standard procedure is to allow a so-called "next friend" (including the attorney) to pursue direct appeal and collateral proceedings aiming to set aside the conviction or sentence. Subpart 3(b) of the Recommendation addresses the definition of competence in such cases, providing that a next friend petition should be allowed when the prisoner has a mental disorder or disability "that significantly impairs his or her capacity to make a rational decision."
Reportedly, 13% of the prisoners executed in the post-Gregg era have been so-called "volunteers."[42] Any meaningful competence inquiry in this context must focus not only on the prisoner's understanding of the consequences of the decision, but also on his or her reasons for wanting to surrender, and on the rationality of the prisoner's thinking and reasoning. In Rees v. Peyton,[43] the U.S. Supreme Court instructed the lower court to determine whether the prisoner had the "capacity to appreciate his position and make a rational choice with respect to continuing or abandoning further litigation or on the other hand whether the prisoner is suffering from a mental disease, disorder or defect which may substantially affect his capacity in the premises."[44] Unfortunately, the two alternative findings mentioned by the Court are not mutually exclusive – a person with a mental disorder that "affects" his or her decision-making may nonetheless be able to appreciate his or her position and make a "rational" choice. For this reason, the lower courts have integrated the Rees formula into a three-step test: (1) does the prisoner have a mental disorder? (2) if so, does this condition prevent the prisoner from understanding his or her legal position and the options available to the prisoner? (3) even if understanding is unimpaired, does the condition nonetheless prevent the prisoner from making a rational choice among the options?[45]
Because the courts have adopted a fairly broad conception of mental disorder (the first step) and the prisoner's understanding of his or her "legal position" (the second step) is hardly ever in doubt in these cases, virtually all the work under the Rees test is done by the third step.[46] Conceptually, the question is relatively straightforward – is the prisoner's decision attributable to the mental disorder or to "rational choice"?
Unequivocal cases of irrationality rarely arise. For example, if an offender suffering from schizophrenia tells his or her attorney to forgo appeals because the future of civilization depends upon the offender's death,[47] the "reason" for the prisoner's choice can comfortably be attributed to the psychotic symptom. However, decisions rooted in delusions are atypical in these cases. The usual case involves articulated reasons that may seem "rational" under the circumstances, such as (a) a desire to take responsibility for one's actions and a belief that one deserves the death penalty or (b) a preference for the death penalty over life imprisonment. The cases that give the courts the most trouble are those in which such apparently "rational" reasons are intertwined with emotional distress (especially depression), feelings of guilt and remorse, and hopelessness. In many cases, choices that may otherwise seem "rational" may be rooted in suicidal motivations. Assuming, for example, that the prisoner is depressed and suicidal but has a genuine desire to take responsibility, how is one to say which motivation "predominates"?
John Blume has studied the prevalence of significant mental disorder among the 106 prisoners who have volunteered for execution. According to Blume, 14 of the "volunteers" had recorded diagnoses of schizophrenia, 23 had recorded diagnoses of depression or bipolar disorder, 10 had records of PTSD, 4 had diagnoses of borderline personality disorder and 2 had been diagnosed with multiple personality disorder. Another 12 had unspecified histories of "mental illness."[48] Given this high prevalence of mental illness, the courts should be more willing than they now are to acknowledge suicidal motivations when they are evident and should be more inclined than they are now to attribute suicidal motivations to mental illness when the clinical evidence of such a link is convincing. The third step of the Rees test would then amount to the following: Is the prisoner who seeks execution able to give plausible reasons for doing so that are clearly not grounded in symptoms of mental disorder?[49] Given the stakes of the decision, a relatively high degree of rationality ought to be required in order to find people competent to make decisions to abandon proceedings concerning the validity of a death sentence.[50]
Prisoners Unable to Assist Counsel in Post-Conviction Proceedings. Subpart 3(c) of the Recommendation addresses the circumstances under which impaired competence to participate in adjudication should affect the initiation or continuation of post-conviction proceedings. The law in this area is both undeveloped and uncertain in many respects. However, some principles have begun to emerge.
Under the laws of many states and the federal Anti-Terrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act (AEDPA), collateral proceedings are barred if they are not initiated within a specified period of time. However, it is undisputed that a prisoner's failure to file within the specified time must be excused if such failure was attributable to a mental disability that impaired the prisoner's ability to recognize the basis for, or to take advantage of, possible collateral remedies. Similarly, the prisoner should be able to lodge new claims, or re-litigate previously raised claims, if the newly available evidence upon which the claim would have been based, or that would have been presented during the earlier proceeding relating to the claim, was unavailable to counsel due to the prisoner's mental disorder or disability.[51]
Assuming, however, that collateral proceedings have been initiated in a timely fashion, the more difficult question is whether, and under what circumstances, a prisoner's mental disability should require suspension of the proceedings. Subpart 3(c) provides that courts should suspend post-conviction proceedings upon proof that a prisoner is incompetent to assist counsel in such proceedings and that the prisoner's participation is necessary for fair resolution of a specific claim.
Thorough post-conviction review of the legality of death sentences has become an integral component of modern death penalty law, analogous in some respects to direct review. Any impediment to thorough collateral review undermines the integrity of the review process and therefore of the death sentence itself. Many issues raised in collateral proceedings can be adjudicated without the prisoner's participation, and these matters should be litigated according to customary practice. However, collateral proceedings should be suspended if the prisoner's counsel makes a substantial and particularized showing that the prisoner's impairment would prevent a fair and accurate resolution of specific claims,[52] and subpart 3(c) so provides.
Where the prisoner's incapacity to assist counsel warrants suspension of the collateral proceedings, it should bar execution as well, just as ABA Standards recommend. ABA Standard 7-5.6 provides that prisoners should not be executed if they cannot understand the nature of the pending proceedings or if they "[lack] sufficient capacity to recognize or understand any fact which might exist which would make the punishment unjust or unlawful, or [lack] the ability to convey such information to counsel or to the court."[53] As the commentary to Standard 7-5.6 indicates, this rule "rests less on sympathy for the sentenced convict than on concern for the integrity of the criminal justice system."[54] Scores of people on death row have been exonerated based on claims of factual innocence, and many more offenders have been removed from death row and given sentences less than death because of subsequent discovery of mitigating evidence. The possibility, however slim, that incompetent individuals may not be able to assist counsel in reconstructing a viable factual or legal claim requires that executions be barred under these circumstances.
Once the post-conviction proceedings have been suspended on grounds of the prisoner's incompetence to assist counsel, should the death sentence remain under an indefinite stay? The situation is analogous to the suspension of criminal proceedings before trial; in that context, the proceedings are typically terminated (and charges are dismissed) after a specified period if a court has found that competence for adjudication is not likely to be restored in the foreseeable future. In the present context, it would be unfair to hold the death sentence in perpetual suspension. A judicial finding that the prisoner's competence to assist counsel is not likely to be restored in the foreseeable future should trigger an automatic reduction of the sentence to the disposition the relevant law imposes on capital offenders when execution is not an option.
Prisoners Unable to Understand the Punishment or its Purpose. In Ford v. Wainwright (1986),[55] the U.S. Supreme Court held that execution of an incompetent prisoner constitutes cruel and unusual punishment proscribed by the Eighth Amendment. Unfortunately, the Court failed to specify a constitutional definition of incompetence or to prescribe the constitutionally required procedures for adjudicating the issue.[56] The Court also failed to set forth a definitive rationale for its holding that might have helped resolve these open questions. Rather it listed, without indicating their relative importance, a number of possible reasons for the competence requirement. These rationales included the need to ensure that the offenders could provide counsel with information that might lead to vacation of sentence; the view that, in the words of Lord Coke, execution of "mad" people is a "miserable spectacle . . . of extream inhumanity and cruelty [that] can be no example to others"; and the notion that retribution cannot be exacted from people who do not understand why they are being executed.[57] Apparently based on the latter rationale, Justice Powell, in his concurring opinion in Ford, stated: "I would hold that the Eighth Amendment forbids the execution only of those who are unaware of the punishment they are about to suffer and why they are to suffer it."[58] Justice Powell pointed out that states are free to preclude execution on other grounds (particularly inability to assist counsel), but most courts and commentators have assumed that the Eighth Amendment requirement is limited to the test stated by Justice Powell. Most commentators have also agreed with Justice Powell's view that the Ford competence requirement is grounded in the retributive purpose of punishment.[59]
There has been some confusion about the meaning of the idea that the prisoner must be able to understand (or be aware of) the nature and purpose for (reasons for) the execution. In Barnard v. Collins,[60] decided by the Fifth Circuit in 1994, the state habeas court had found that Barnard's "perception of the reason for his conviction and impending execution is at times distorted by a delusional system in which he attributes anything negative that happens to him to a conspiracy of Asians, Jews, Blacks, homosexuals and the Mafia."[61] Despite the fact that Barnard's understanding of the reason for his execution was impaired by delusions, the Fifth Circuit concluded that his awareness that "his pending execution was because he had been found guilty of the crime" was sufficient to support the state habeas court's legal conclusion that he was competent to be executed. [62]
In order to emphasize the need for a deeper understanding of the state's justifying purpose for the execution, subpart 3(d) of the Recommendation would require that an offender not only must be "aware" of the nature and purpose of punishment but also must "appreciate" its personal application in the offender's own case – that is, why it is being imposed on the offender. This formulation is analogous to the distinction often drawn between a "factual understanding" and a "rational understanding" of the reason for the execution.[63] If, as is generally assumed, the primary purpose of the competence-to-be-executed requirement is to vindicate the retributive aim of punishment, then offenders should have more than a shallow understanding of why they are being executed.
Whether a person found incompetent to be executed should be treated to restore competence implicates not only the prisoner's constitutional right to refuse treatment but also the ethical integrity of the mental health professions.[64] Some courts have decided that the government may forcibly medicate incompetent individuals if necessary to render them competent to be executed, on the ground that once an individual is fairly convicted and sentenced to death, the state's interest in carrying out the sentence outweighs any individual interest in avoiding medication.[65] However, treating a condemned prisoner, especially over his or her objection, for the purpose of enabling the state to execute the prisoner strikes many observers as barbaric and also violates fundamental ethical norms of the mental health professions.
Mental health professionals are nearly unanimous in the view that treatment with the purpose or likely effect of enabling the state to carry out an execution of a person who has been found incompetent for execution is unethical, whether or not the prisoner objects, except in two highly restricted circumstances (an advance directive by the prisoner while competent requesting such treatment or a compelling need to alleviate extreme suffering).[66] Because treatment is unethical, it is not "medically appropriate" and is therefore constitutionally impermissible when a prisoner objects under the criteria enunciated by the Supreme Court in Sell v. United States[67] and Washington v. Harper.[68] As the Louisiana Supreme Court observed in Perry v. Louisiana,[69] medical treatment to restore execution competence "is antithetical to the basic principles of the healing arts," fails to "measurably contribute to the social goals of capital punishment," and "is apt to be administered erroneously, arbitrarily or capriciously."[70]
There is only one sensible policy here: a death sentence should be automatically commuted to a lesser punishment (the precise nature of which will be governed by the jurisdiction's death penalty jurisprudence) after a prisoner has been found incompetent for execution.[71] Maryland has so prescribed,[72] and subpart 3(d) of the Recommendation embraces this view. Once an offender is found incompetent to be executed, execution should no longer be a permissible punishment.
The current judicial practice is to entertain Ford claims only when execution is genuinely imminent. Should courts be willing to adjudicate these claims at an earlier time? Assuming that a judicial finding of incompetence – whenever rendered – would permanently bar execution (as proposed above), subpart 3(d) provides that Ford adjudications should be available only when legal challenges to the validity of the conviction and sentence have been exhausted, and execution has been scheduled.[73]
Procedures: While this paragraph contemplates that hearings will have to be held to determine competency to proceed and competency to be executed, it does not make any recommendations with respect to procedures. Federal constitutional principles and state law will govern whether the necessary decisions must be made by a judge or a jury, what burdens and standards of proof apply, and the scope of other rights to be accorded offenders. Additionally, in any proceedings necessary to make these determinations, the victim's next-of-kin should be accorded rights recognized by law, which may include the right to be present during the proceedings, the right to be heard, and the right to confer with the government's attorney. Victim's next-of-kin should be treated with fairness and respect throughout the process.

Respectfully Submitted,
Paul M. Igasaki, Chair
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities

Michael S. Pasano, Chair
Criminal Justice Section

Scott C. LaBarre, Chair
Commission on Mental and Physical Disability Law

James E. Coleman, Jr., Chair
Death Penalty Moratorium Implementation Project

Terri Lynn Mascherin, Chair
Death Penalty Representation Project

August 2006
GENERAL INFORMATION FORM

Submitting Entity: Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities

Submitted By: Paul M. Igasaki, Chair
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities

1. Summary of the Recommendation

The Recommendation, without taking a position supporting or opposing the death penalty, calls upon each jurisdiction that imposes capital punishment to implement the following policies and procedures:
1) defendants should not be executed or sentenced to death if, at the time of the offense, they had significant limitations in both their intellectual functioning and adaptive behavior, as expressed in conceptual, social, and practical adaptive skills, resulting from mental retardation, dementia, or a traumatic brain injury;
2) defendants should not be executed or sentenced to death if, at the time of the offense, they had a severe mental disorder or disability that significantly impaired their capacity (a) to appreciate the nature, consequences or wrongfulness of their conduct, (b) to exercise rational judgment in relation to conduct, or (c) to conform their conduct to the requirements of the law. A disorder manifested primarily by repeated criminal conduct or attributable solely to the acute effects of voluntary use of alcohol or other drugs does not, standing alone, constitute a mental disorder or disability for purposes of this provision; and
3) A death sentence should not be carried out if the prisoner has a mental disorder or disability that significantly impairs his or her capacity (i) to make a rational decision to forgo or terminate post-conviction proceedings available to challenge the validity of the conviction or sentence, (ii) to understand or communicate pertinent information, or otherwise assist counsel, in relation to specific claims bearing on the validity of the conviction or sentence that cannot be fairly resolved without the prisoner's participation, or (iii) to understand the nature and purpose of the punishment, or to appreciate the reason for its imposition in the prisoner's own case. [See resolution for more detail re paragraph 3.]

2. Approval by Submitting Entity
The Council of the Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities approved the Report with Recommendation during its Midyear Meeting on Friday, Feb.10, 2006.

The Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities has been advised that the following have agreed to co-sponsor the proposed resolution:

Criminal Justice Section
Commission on Mental and Physical Disability Law
Death Penalty Representation Project
Death Penalty Moratorium Project

Has This or a Similar Recommendation Been Submitted to the House of Delegates Board of Governors Previously?

No.

3. What Existing Association Policies Are Relevant to this Proposed Resolution and Would They Be Affected by Its Adoption?

The ABA has adopted numerous policies addressing the need for fair implementation of capital punishment, including:

· Urging jurisdictions that impose capital punishment not to carry out the death penalty without guaranteeing fairness, due process, and minimum risk to innocent persons. 2/97

· Urging that no person with mental retardation, as defined by the American Association on Mental Retardation, should be sentenced to death or executed and supporting enactment of legislation prohibiting the execution of defendants with mental retardation. 2/89

· Opposing discrimination in capital sentencing on the basis of race. 2/89

· Opposing the imposition of capital punishment upon any person for any offense committed while under the age of 18. 8/83

This proposed resolution would build upon these existing policies by urging each jurisdiction that imposes capital punishment to implement the policies and procedures outlined in Section 1 above.

In addition, Paragraph 2 of the proposed resolution includes language derived from ABA Criminal Justice Standard 7-6.1. Moreover, paragraph 3 of the proposed resolution clarifies and supplements ABA Criminal Justice Standards 7-5.6 and 7-5.7.


4. What Urgency Exists that Requires Action at this Meeting of the House?

Many commentators have said, in the wake of Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304 (2002) and Roper v. Simmons, 125 U.S. 1183 (2005), that the next major issue regarding capital punishment is to what extent, if any, should people with mental illness be exempt from executions. It is important that the ABA have an important voice in dealing with this issue, particularly because this proposal takes a nuanced approach. That is, it does not say that everyone who has a mental illness should be exempt from capital punishment, but rather considers the type of mental illness and how it contributed to the capital crime. The resolution also deals with several important issues that arise when death row inmates have mental illness that may affect their ability competently to waive appeals, to assist their counsel or to be executed.

The proposed resolution is identical to the language adopted by the American Psychiatric Association and the American Psychological Association, except for two clarifying changes made in paragraph 3 of the proposed resolution to specifically state that if the death penalty is vacated, the sentence would be the next most severe punishment.

5. Status of Legislation

In 2002, the United States Supreme Court held that it is unconstitutional to execute a person with mental retardation, in Atkins v. Virginia. Subsequent to Atkins, proposed legislation to deal with the application of the death penalty to people with other disabilities have been introduced in some states.

6. Cost to the Association (Both Direct and Indirect Costs)

Adoption of this proposed resolution would result in only minor indirect costs associated with Government Affairs and Section staff time devoted to the policy subject matter as part of the staff members’ overall substantive responsibilities.

7. Disclosure of Interest

There are no known conflicts of interest.

8. Referrals

By copy of this form, the Report with Recommendation will be referred to the following additional entities, including all Sections and Divisions:

Section of Administrative Law and Regulatory Practice
Section of Antitrust Law
Section of Business Law
Section of Dispute Resolution
Section of Environment, Energy, and Resources
Section of Family Law
General Practice, Solo and Small Firm Section
Government and Public Sector Lawyers Division
Section of Intellectual Property Law
Section of International Law and Practice
Section of Labor and Employment Law
Law Practice Management Section
Section of Legal Education and Admissions to the Bar
Section of Litigation
Section of Public Contract Law
Section of Public Utility, Communications and Transportation Law
Section of Real Property, Probate and Trust Law
Section of Science and Technology Law
Section of State and Local Government Law
Section of Taxation
Tort and Insurance Practice Section
Judicial Division
Law Student Division
Senior Lawyers Division
Young Lawyers Division
Commission on Domestic Violence
Commission on Homelessness and Poverty
Commission on Law and Aging
Commission on Women in the Profession

9. Contact Person (Prior to Meeting)

Ronald J. Tabak
Skadden, Arps, Slate, Meagher & Flom
4 Times Square, 24th Floor
New York, NY 10036-6522
Tel: (212) 735-2226
Fax: (917) 777-2226
Email: rtabak@probonolaw.com

Tanya Terrell-Collier, Director
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities
740 15th Street, NW
Washington, DC 20005
Tel: (202) 662-1030
Fax: (202) 662-1031
Email: terrellt@staff.abanet.org


10. Contact Person (Who Will Present the Report to the House)

C. Elisia Frazier, Delegate
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities
International Paper Company
Senior Counsel – Woods Products Division
6400 Poplar Avenue
Memphis, TN 38197
Tel : (901) 419-3801
Email : c.elisia.frazier@ipaper.com

Richard M. Macias
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities
Richard Macias & Associates
2741 Prewett Street
PO Box 31569
Los Angeles, CA 90031
Tel : (323) 224-3906
Email : rmmacias@aol.com

11. Contact Person Regarding Amendments to this Recommendation
C. Elisia Frazier, Delegate
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities
International Paper Company
Senior Counsel – Woods Products Division
6400 Poplar Avenue
Memphis, TN 38197
Tel : (901) 419-3801
Email : c.elisia.frazier@ipaper.com

Richard M. Macias
Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities
Richard Macias & Associates
2741 Prewett Street
PO Box 31569
Los Angeles, CA 90031
Tel : (323) 224-3906
Email : rmmacias@aol.com

[1] The Task Force's members are Dr. Michael Abramsky; Dr. Xavier F. Amador; Michael Allen, Esq.; Donna Beavers; Professor John H. Blume; Professor Richard J. Bonnie; Colleen Quinn Brady, Esq.; Richard Burr, Esq.; Dr. Joel A. Dvoskin; Dr. James R. Eisenberg; Professor I. Michael Greenberger; Dr. Kirk S. Heilbrun; Ronald Honberg, Esq.; Ralph Ibson; Dr. Matthew B. Johnson; Professor Dorean M. Koenig; Dr. Diane T. Marsh; Hazel Moran; John Parry, Esq.; Professor Jennifer Radden; Professor Laura Lee Rovner; Robyn S. Shapiro, Esq.; Professor Christopher Slobogin; and Ronald J. Tabak, Esq. Drs. Paul S. Appelbaum, Howard V. Zonana and Jeffrey Metzner also contributed significantly to the Task Force's deliberations and recommendations.,
[2] See Am. Psychiatric Ass'n, Diminished Responsibility in Capital Sentencing; Death Sentences for Persons with Dementia or Traumatic Brain Injury; Mentally Ill Prisoners on Death Row: available at http://www.psych.org/edu/other_res/lib_archives/archives/200406.pdf, 200508.pdf, 200505.pdf.
[3] See American Psychological Association, Excerpt from the Council of Representatives 2005 Meeting Minutes (Feb. 18-20, 2005); Excerpt from the Council of Representatives 2006 Meeting Minutes (Feb. 17-19, 2006).
[4] The recommendation being presented to the House of Delegates is identical to the wording approved by these other groups, except that minor changes have been made to paragraph 3(c) and 3(d) to remove any potential doubt that, where either provision applies, the sentence would be the one that would be applicable in a capital case in situations in which the death penalty is not a sentencing option.
[5] 536 U.S. 304 (2003).
[6] Id. at 313-17.
[7] Id. at 318-20.
[8] Manual of the American Association of Mental Retardation 13 (10th ed., 2002).
[9] See American Psychiatric Association, Diagnostic and Statistical Manual 49 (text rev. 4th ed. 2000) (hereafter DSM-IV-TR).
[10] 536 U.S. at 308 n.3. Death Penalty Info. Ctr., State Statutes Prohibiting the Death Penalty for People with Mental Retardation, www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/article.php?scid (describing state laws).
[11] DSM-IV-TR, supra note 9, at 43 (stating that people with "mild" mental retardation develop academic skills up to the sixth‑grade level, amounting to the maturity of a twelve year‑old). For more on the definition of retardation, see James W. Ellis, Mental Retardation and the Death Penalty: A Guide to State Legislative Issues, 27 Men. & Phys. Dis. L. Rep. 11-24 (2003); Richard J. Bonnie, The APA's Resource Document on Mental Retardation and Capital Sentencing: Implementing Atkins v. Virginia, 32 J. Am. Acad. Psychiat. & L. 304­, 308 (2004).
[12] DSM-IV-TR, supra note 9, at 135 (describing symptoms of dementia).
[13] Compare id., at 135 (describing symptoms of dementia) with id. at 46 (symptoms of mental retardation).
[14] 125 S.Ct. 1183 (2005).
[15] 536 U.S. at 318.
[16] Id. at 319.
[17] Id.
[18] 125 S.Ct. at 1196.
[19] Id. (quoting Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.S. 815, 837 (1988)).
[20] See DSM-IV-TR, supra note 9, at 25-26 (distinguishing Axis I diagnoses from Axis II diagnoses).
[21] See id., ­at 275-76 (schizophrenia); 301 (delusional disorders); 332-33 (mood disorder with psychotic features); 125 (delirium); 477 (dissociative disorders).
[22] See id., at 652. Other Axis II diagnoses that might produce psychotic-like symptoms include Autistic Disorder, id. at 75, and Asperger's Disorder. Id. at 84.
[23] This is a fairly common perception of people with schizophrenia who commit violent acts. See Dale E. McNiel, The Relationship Between Aggressive Attributional Style and Violence by Psychiatric Patients, 71 J. Consulting & Clinical Psychology 404, 405 (2003).
[24] Cf. People v. Schmidt, 216 N.Y. 324, 110 N.E. 945 (1915) (stating that if a person has "an insane delusion that God has appeared to [him] and ordained the commission of a crime, we think it cannot be said of the offender that he knows the act to be wrong).
[25] These offenders would not have the mens rea for murder, and perhaps not even meet the voluntary act requirement for crime. See Wayne LaFave, Criminal Law 405 (3d ed. 2000) (describing the voluntary act requirement under the common law).
[26] See, e.g., Herbert Fingarette & Ann Fingarette Hasse, Mental Disabilities and Criminal Responsibility 218 (1979); Michael Moore, Law and Psychiatry: Rethinking the Relationship 244-245 (1985); Stephen J. Morse, Immaturity and Irresponsibility, 88 J. Crim. L. & Criminology 15, 24 (1997); Robert F. Schopp, Automatism, Insanity and the Psychology of Criminal Responsibility: A Philosophical Inquiry 215 (1991).
[27] For a description of the Yates case, see Deborah W. Denno, Who is Andrea Yates? A Short Story About Insanity, 10 Duke J. Gender L. & Pol'y 37 (2003).
[28] DSM-IV-TR, supra note 9, at 332-33.
[29] Id. at 650 et. seq. (defining as a symptom of antisocial personality disorder "failure to conform to social norms with respect to lawful behaviors as indicated by repeatedly performing acts that are grounds for arrest).
[30] See American Law Institute, Model Penal Code § 4.01(2) and commentary (draft, 1962) (stating that "mental disease or defect as used in the insanity formulation does not include "abnormality manifested only by repeated or otherwise anti-social conduct).
[31] See generally LaFave, supra note 25, at 415-16.
[32] See Jeffrey L. Kirchmeier, A Tear in the Eye of the Law: Mitigating Factors and the Progression Toward a Disease Model of Criminal Justice, 83 Oregon L. Rev. 631, 679 n.237 (2004) (listing statutes and judicial decisions from over a dozen states that have recognized intoxication as a mitigating circumstance).
[33] In Montana v. Egelhoff, 518 U.S. 37 (1996), a plurality of the Supreme Court held that the voluntary intoxication defense is not constitutionally required. Id. at 38. At least 13 states now reject the voluntary intoxication defense. See Molly McDonough, Sobering Up, 88 A.B.A. J. 28 (2002).
[34] See, e.g., DSM-IV-TR, supra note 9, at 170 (describing dementia due to prolonged substance abuse).
[35] The language in 2(a) and 2(c), for instance, is almost identical to the language in the Model Penal Code's insanity formulation. See Model Penal Code, supra note 30, at § 4.01(1).
[36] Today, five states do not have an insanity defense, another twenty-five do not recognize volitional impairment as a basis for the defense, and many states define the cognitive prong in terms of an inability to "know" (as opposed to "appreciate") the wrongfulness of the act or, as is true in federal court, leave out the word "substantial@ in the phrase Alack of substantial capacity to appreciate@ in the Model Penal Code formulation. See ralph reisner et al., law and the mental health system: civil and criminal aspects 534-36 (4th ed. 2004).
[37] See generally Michael L. Perlin, "The Borderline Which Separated You from Me@: The Insanity Defense, the Authoritarian Spirit, the Fear of Faking, and the Culture of Punishment, 82 Iowa L. Rev. 1375 (1997) (exploring reasons for hostility to the insanity defense).
[38] See Ellen Fels Berkman, Mental Illness as an Aggravating Circumstance in Capital Sentencing, 89 Colum. L. Rev. 291, 297 (1989) (noting that "nearly two dozen jurisdictions list as a statutory mitigating circumstance the fact that the defendant's capacity to appreciate the criminality of her conduct was substantially impaired, often as a result of mental defect or disease and that "an equally high number of states includes extreme mental or emotional disturbance' as a mitigating factor).
[39] See generally sheldon glueck, mental disorder and the criminal law (1925).
[40] See, e.g., Model Penal Code, supra note 30, at § 210.6.
[41] See, e.g., Gilmore v. Utah, 429 U.S.1012 (1977).
[42] John Blume, Killing the Willing: "Volunteers, Suicide and Competency, 103 mich. l. rev. 939, 959 (2005).
[43] 384 U.S. 312 (1966) (case remanded for competency determination after condemned prisoner directed attorney to withdraw petition for certiorari).
[44] Id. at 314.
[45] See, e.g., Hauser v. Moore, 223 F.3d 1316, 1322 (11th Cir. 2000); Rumbaugh v. Procunier, 753 F.2d 395 (5th Cir 1985).
[46] Richard J. Bonnie, Mentally Ill Prisoners on Death Row: Unsolved Puzzles for Courts and Legislatures, 54 Cath. Univ. L. Rev.1169 (2005).
[47] Cf. Illinois v. Haynes, 737 N.E.2d 169, 178 (Ill. 2000); In re Heidnick, 720 A. 2d 1016 (Pa 1998).
[48] Blume, supra note 41, Appendix B, at 989-96. The text refers only to significant mental disorders that could have distorted the prisoner's reasoning process and impaired capacity for Arational choice.@ In addition to these cases, Blume reports that 20 of these prisoners had histories of substance abuse unaccompanied by any other mental disorder diagnosis, another 6 had personality disorders (with or without substance abuse) and 4 had sexual impulse disorders.
[49] See Bonnie, supra note 46, at 1187-88. A more demanding approach would ask whether the prisoner is able to give plausible reasons that reflect authentic values and enduring preferences.
[50] See Richard J. Bonnie, The Dignity of the Condemned, 74 va.l. rev. 1363, 1388-89 (1988); Cf. Richard J. Bonnie, The Competence of Criminal Defendants: Beyond Dusky and Drope, 47 univ. miami l. rev. 539, 579-80 (1993).
[51] See, e.g., Council v. Catoe, 359 S.C. 120, 597 S.E.2d 782, 787 (2004); Commonwealth v. Haag, 809 A.2d 271, 285 (PA, 2001).
[52] Council v. Catoe, 359 S.C. 120, 597 S.E.2d 782, 787 (A[T]he default rule is that [post-conviction review] hearings must proceed even though a petitioner is incompetent. For issues requiring the petitioner's competence to assist his [post-conviction] counsel, such as a fact-based challenge to his defense counsel's conduct at trial, the [post-conviction] judge may grant a continuance, staying review of these issues until petitioner regains his competence.); Carter v. State, 706 So.2d 873, 875-77 (Fla. 1997); State v. Debra, 523 N.W.2d 727 (Wisc. 1994) (non-capital case); People v. Kelly, 822 P.2d 385, 413 (Cal. 1992).
[53] ABA Criminal Justice Mental Health Standards 290 (1989).
[54] Id, at 291.
[55] 477 U.S. 399.
[56] State courts have disagreed about the procedures required to make Ford competence determinations. A sensible outline of the required procedures appears in the ABA Standard 7.5-7 and the Sixth Circuit's decision in Coe v. Bell, 209 F.3d 815 (6th Cir. 2000). The prisoner is entitled to state-subsidized counsel and expert assessment once the prisoner presents evidence raising a significant doubt about his competence. The issue should be adjudicated at hearing before a judge at which the prisoner bears the burden of proving his incompetence by a preponderance of the evidence. See also Paul F. Enzinna and Jana L. Gill, Capital Punishment and the Incompetent: Procedures for Determining Competency to be Executed after Ford v. Wainwright, 41 fla. l. rev. 115 (1989).
[57] Id. at 406-08.
[58] Id. at 422 (Powell, J., concurring).
[59] See Barbara Ward, Competency for Execution: Problems in Law and Psychiatry, 14 fla. st. univ. l. rev. 35, 49-56 (1986); Christopher Slobogin, Mental Illness and the Death Penalty, 24 men. & phys. l. rep. 667, 675-77 (2000).
[60] 13 F.3d 871 (5th Cir, 1994).
[61] Id. at 876.
[62] Id.
[63] See Martin v. Florida, 515 So. 2d 189, 190 (Fla. 1987).
[64] Kirk S. Heilbrun, Michael L. Radelet, Joel A. Dvoskin, The Debate on Treating Individuals Incompetent for Execution, 149 american journal of psychiatry 596 (1992); Richard J. Bonnie, Dilemmas in Administering the Death Penalty: Conscientious Abstention, Professional Ethics and the Needs of the Legal System, 14 law & human behavior 67 (1990).
[65] Singleton v. Norris, 319 F.3d 1018 (8th Cir.) (en banc), cert denied, 124 S. Ct. 74 (2003).
[66] See Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association, Physician Participation in Capital Punishment, 270 JAMA365 (1993); American Psychiatric Association and American Medical Association, Amicus Brief in Support of Petitioner in Perry v. Louisiana, 498 U.S. 38 (1990); Richard J. Bonnie, Medical Ethics and the Death Penalty, 20 hastings center report, may/june, 1990, 12, 15-17.
[67] 539 U.S. 166 (2003).
[68] 494 U.S. 210 (1990).
[69] 610 So.2d 746 (La. 1992).
[70] Id. at 751.
[71] A state could try to restore a prisoner's competence without medical treatment, but the prospects of an enduring change in the prisoner's condition are slight.
[72] Md. Code of Correctional Services, 3-904(a)(2), (d)(1).
[73] This does not mean that no litigation challenging the validity of the sentence can be simultaneously occurring. For all practical purposes, "exhaustion" means that one full sequence of state post-conviction review and federal habeas review have occurred where, as in most jurisdictions, no execution date set during the initial round of collateral review is a "real" date. Given the many procedural barriers to successive petitions for collateral review, an execution date set after the completion of the initial round may be a "real" date, even if a successive petition has been filed or is being planned. In such a case, the state may contest the prisoner's request for a stay of execution. A Ford claim should be considered on its merits in such a case, and it should be considered earlier on in a jurisdiction where a "real" execution date is set during the initial round of collateral review